Engineering and Ethics – Week #6 Lecture1

Risk and Liability in Engineering

Introduction

Safety is always a concern for engineers. This module talks about how engineers need to deal with issues of safety and risk, especially when they involve possible liability for harm? An important fact is that; Engineering necessarily involves risk, and risk changes as technology changes. One cannot avoid risk simply by remaining with tried and true designs, but new technologies involve risks that may not be as well understood, potentially increasing the chance of failure or even introducing a previously unknown mode of failure.

Safety and risk obviously are related ideas; engineers work to make their designs safe. Engineers must try to achieve designs that meet cost constraints so they will be affordable and must work to design and operate engineered systems in ways that are acceptably safe, which is to say in ways that do not introduce unacceptable risks. To determine acceptable levels of safety in engineering systems, we instead try to identify the risks of harm and find ways to quantify those risks. When the level of risk is determined to be acceptable, we can conclude the design in question is acceptably safe. Generally acceptable levels of safety are codified in the specific design codes for the product or system in question, and the designing engineer only has to adhere to accepted practice, but when the proposed design deviates from accepted practice in some important parameter, it may be that the proposed design may introduce previously unidentified risks.

In this lecture, three different approaches to risk and safety are presented, all of which are important in determining public policy regarding risk. The issues of risk communication and public policy concerning risk are then examined. Then difficulties in both estimating and preventing risk from the engineering perspective are discussed. Finally, some of the legal issues surrounding risk protecting engineers from undue liability and different approaches of tort law and criminal law to risk are explained.

The Engineer’s approach to Risk

Risk as the Product of the Probability and Magnitude of Harm

In order to assess risk, an engineer must identify the risk and quantify it. Engineers define risk as the product of the likelihood of an event and the magnitude of the resulting harm. A relatively slight harm that is highly likely might then constitute a greater risk than a more serious harm that is far less likely. When engineers quantify risk in this way, they must observe that the units of this quantity will depend on the exact harm being considered, so they must be cautious not to quantitatively compare or add risk quantities that have different units. Engineers have traditionally thought of harms in terms of things that can be relatively easily quantified, namely, as impairments of our physical and economic well-being or the public health, safety, or welfare. Risk is something that can be objectively measured—namely, the product of the likelihood and the magnitude of harm.

Defining Acceptable Risk

The engineering concept of risk focuses on the factual issues of the probability and magnitude of harm and contains no implicit evaluation of whether a risk is morally acceptable. In order to determine whether a risk is acceptable, engineers and risk experts considering engineering solutions often use a cost-benefit analysis that is fundamentally a utilitarian approach. The cost-benefit approach compares the costs, including the quantified costs of the imposed risks of the engineering actions under consideration, with the benefits of the actions. Then the engineering solution that maximizes net benefits (benefits minus costs) consistent with economic and other constraints is typically selected. Given the earlier definition of risk as the product of the probability and the consequences of harm, one can state the engineer’s criterion of acceptable risk in the following way: an acceptable risk is one in which the product of the probability and magnitude of the harm is equaled or exceeded by the product of the probability and magnitude of the benefit. Cost-benefit analysis is systematic, offers a degree of objectivity, and provides a way of comparing risks and benefits by the use of a common measure—namely, monetary cost.

The Capabilities Approach to Identifying Harm and Benefit

A capability is the real freedom of individuals to achieve a functioning, and it refers to the real options he or she has available. Capabilities are constituent elements of individual well-being. Often, people’s preferences or choices are used to measure satisfaction. Utilities are assigned to represent a preference function. In determining a risk, the first step is to identify the important capabilities that might be damaged by a disaster. Then, to quantify the ways in which the capabilities might be damaged, we must find some “indicators” that are correlated with the capabilities. Then, a summary index is constructed by combining the information provided by each normalized indicator, creating a hazard index (HI). Finally, to put the HI into the relevant context, its value is divided by the population affected by the hazard, creating the hazard impact index, which measures the hazard impact per person.

Some of the benefits of using capabilities-based approach in identifying the societal impact of a hazard are discussed. First, capabilities capture the adverse effects and opportunities of hazards beyond the consequences traditionally considered. Second, since capabilities are constitutive aspects of individual well-being, this approach focuses our attention on what should be our primary concern in assessing the societal impact of a hazard. Third, the capabilities-based approach offers a more accurate way to measure the actual impact of a hazard on individuals’ well-being. Fourth, rather than considering diverse consequences, which increases the difficulty of quantification, the capabilities-based approach requires considering a few properly selected capabilities.

Communicating Risk and Public Policy

Communicating Risk to Public

Engineers define risk as the product of the magnitude and likelihood of harm and are sympathetic with the utilitarian way of assessing acceptable risk. The professional codes require engineers to hold paramount the safety, health, and welfare of the public, so engineers have an obligation to minimize risk. However, in determining an acceptable level of risk for engineering works, they are likely to use, or at least be sympathetic with, the cost-benefit approach. The lay public comes to issues of risk from a very different approach. Part of the difference in approach results from the tendency to combine judgments of the likelihood and acceptability of risk. More important, the lay public considers free and informed consent and equitable distribution of risk (or appropriate compensation) to be important in the determination of acceptable risk.

In light of different perspectives, the following guidelines have been proposes for engineers in risk communication:

1.     Engineers, in communicating risk to the public, should be aware that the public’s approach to risk is not the same as that of the risk expert. In particular, “risky” cannot be identified with a measure of the probability of harm. Thus, engineers should not say “risk” when they mean “probability of harm.” They should use the two terms independently.

2.     Engineers should be wary of saying, “There is no such thing as zero risk.” The public often uses “zero risk” to indicate not that something involves no probability of harm but that it is a familiar risk that requires no further deliberation.

3.     Engineers should be aware that the public does not always trust experts and believes that experts have sometimes been wrong in the past. Therefore, engineers, in presenting risks to the public, should be careful to acknowledge the possible limitations in their position. They should also be aware that laypeople may rely on their own values in deciding whether or not to base action on an expert’s prediction of probable outcomes.

4.     Engineers should be aware that government regulators have a special obligation to protect the public, and that this obligation may require them to take into account considerations other than a strict cost-benefit approach. Although public policy should take into account cost-benefit considerations, it should take into account the special obligations of government regulators.

5.     Professional engineering organizations, such as the professional societies, have a special obligation to present information regarding technological risk. They must present information that is as objective as possible regarding probabilities of harm.

Building Codes

The local building codes is the best way of reflecting on the public policy which specify factors of safety and construction steps that are required in the area. Building codes have the status of law and may not be changed without public hearings and legislative action. The legislature will often appoint a committee of experts to propose a new building code or necessary changes in an existing one.

One of the more important ways professional engineers show a concern for the general public (and their safety) is in carrying out the local building code requirements in designing such things as buildings, elevators, escalators, bridges, walkways, roads, and overpasses. When a responsible engineer recognizes a violation of a building code in a design and does not object to it, the engineer bears some responsibility for any injuries or deaths that result. Similarly, when an engineer learns of a proposed change in a building code that he or she is convinced creates danger for the public and does nothing to prevent this change, the engineer bears some responsibility for any harm done.

Difficulties in determining the cause and likelihood of harm

In actual practice, estimating risk or risk assessment involves an uncertain prediction of the probability of harm. Some of the methods of estimating risk are: Limitations in Identifying Failure modes, Limitations due to Tight Coupling and Complex Interactions and Normalizing Deviance and Self-Deception.

Engineer’s Liability for Risk

Risk is difficult to estimate and that engineers are often tempted to allow anomalies to accumulate without taking remedial action, and even to expand the scope of acceptable risk to accommodate them. We have also seen that there are different and sometimes incompatible approaches to the definition of acceptable risk as exhibited by risk experts, laypeople, and government regulators.

Another issue that raises ethical and professional concerns for engineers regards legal liability for risk. There are at least two issues here. One is that the standards of proof in tort law and science are different, and this produces an interesting ethical conflict. Another issue is that in protecting the public from unnecessary risk, engineers may themselves incur legal liabilities. Let us consider each of these issues.

The Standards of Tort Law

Litigation that seeks redress from harm most commonly appeals to the law of torts, which deals with injuries to one person caused by another, usually as a result of fault or negligence of the injuring party. Many of the most famous legal cases involving claims of harm from technology have been brought under the law of torts. The major ethical question, however, is whether we should be more concerned with protecting the rights of plaintiffs who may have been unjustly harmed or with promoting economic efficiency and protecting defendants against unjust charges of harm. This is the ethical issue at the heart of the debate.

Protecting Engineers from liability

The apparent ease with which proximate cause can be established in tort law may suggest that the courts should impose a more stringent standard of acceptable risk. But other aspects of the law afford the public less protection than it deserves. For example, the threat of legal liability can inhibit engineers from adequately protecting the public from risk. Engineers in private practice may face especially difficult considerations regarding liability and risk, and in some cases, they may need increased protection from liability. If engineers were free to specify safety measures without being held liable for their neglect or improper use, they could more easily fulfill one aspect of their responsibility to protect the safety of the public.

Becoming a responsible engineering regarding risk

The obligation of engineers is to be ethically responsible with regard to risk. The first step in the process of becoming ethically responsible about risk is to be aware of the fact that risk is often difficult to estimate and can be increased in ways that may be subtle and treacherous. The second step is to be aware that there are different approaches to the determination of acceptable risk. In particular, engineers have a strong bias toward quantification in their approach to risk, which may make them insufficiently sensitive to the concerns of the lay public and even the government regulators. The third step is to assume their responsibility, as the experts in technology, to communicate issues regarding risk to the public, with the full awareness that both the public and government regulators have a somewhat different agenda with regard to risk.

Engineers and risk experts look at risk in a somewhat different way from others in society. For engineers, risk is the product of the likelihood and magnitude of harm. An acceptable risk is one in which the product of the probability and magnitude of the harm is equaled or exceeded by the product of the probability and magnitude of the benefit, and no other option exists where the product of the probability and magnitude of the benefit is substantially greater. A risk is acceptable if the probability is sufficiently small that the adverse effect of a hazard will fall below a threshold of the minimum level of capabilities attainment that is acceptable in principle.

Engineers need to protect themselves from undue liability for risk, but this need sometimes raises important issues for social policy. The problems engineers have in protecting themselves from unjust liabilities while protecting the public from harm are illustrated by the use of trench boxes. Finally, a principle of acceptable risk provides some guidance in determining when a risk is within the bounds of moral permissibility.

Summary

Engineers and risk experts look at risk in a somewhat different way from others in society. For engineers, risk is the product of the likelihood and magnitude of harm. An acceptable risk is one in which the product of the probability and magnitude of the harm is equaled or exceeded by the product of the probability and magnitude of the benefit, and no other option exists where the product of the probability and magnitude of the benefit is substantially greater. In calculating harms and benefits, engineers have traditionally identified harm with factors that are relatively easily quantified, such as economic losses and loss of life. The “capabilities” approach attempts to make these calculations more sophisticated by developing a more adequate way of measuring the harms and benefits from disasters to overall well-being, which it defines in terms of the capabilities of people to live the kind of life they value. A risk is acceptable if the probability is sufficiently small that the adverse effect of a hazard will fall below a threshold of the minimum level of capabilities attainment that is acceptable in principle.

Engineers, and especially professional engineering societies, have an obligation to contribute to public debate on risk by supplying expert information and by recognizing that the perspectives in the public debate will comprise more than the perspective of the risk expert.

Engineers need to protect themselves from undue liability for risk, but this need sometimes raises important issues for social policy. One issue is the conflict between the standards of science and tort law. The standard of proof in tort law for whether something causes a harm is the preponderance of evidence, but the standard of evidence in science is much higher. The lower standard of tort law tends to protect the rights of plaintiffs who may have been unjustly harmed, and the higher standard of science tends to protect defendants and perhaps promote economic efficiency. The problems engineers have in protecting themselves from unjust liabilities while protecting the public from harm are illustrated by the use of trench boxes. Finally, a principle of acceptable risk provides some guidance in determining when a risk is within the bounds of moral permissibility

 

Title: Grantham Copyright - Description: Grantham Copyright 2018